The front door is unfamiliar, just one more chunk of wood among the countless doors that I pass by unthinkingly every day. I hesitate, listen for sounds of life from within, but everything is quiet, and the door yields soundlessly to my touch. It takes a while to find a light switch, but once I do a warm glow illuminates the flat. I potter for a while before settling, perusing the book shelf, scanning the title of the novel by the bed, noting the dubstep on the cd rack, wondering if the fridge will yield milk, or beer, or only mould. ‘This lamp is nice,’ I think, ‘maybe it would suit my own house,’ before showering, lathering my skin with a stranger’s scent, and then climbing into her bed to go to sleep.
No, I haven’t taken up stalking female celebrities. I’m
speaking instead about one of my recent adventures in Airbnb-ing. This
peer-to-peer web service matches up users who need a place to stay with
providers who are willing to rent out their private home for the night. The
provider in this case wasn’t going to be in town, so she emailed me her address
and door code in exchange for a modest fee, and there I was making myself
comfortable in the home of someone I had never, and probably would never, meet.
What’s the problem?
For a while, the received wisdom of the evolution of
cooperation literature has been that such exchanges like the ones that take
place via Airbnb shouldn’t happen. Each
participant in such an interaction accepts only a modest benefit (a place to
sleep, a small fee) in exchange for considerable risks. The vendor might have
wildly exaggerated the assets of the accommodation. She might have provided a
false door code, just to get my money. I might have entered a trap, in which
the vendor was waiting to rob me in my sleep, or worse. On the other hand, once
I’m inside her home, what is to stop me from helping myself to her shampoo,
nicking the lamp, changing the locks and refusing to leave? Users have reported having all kinds of
terrible experiences using Airbnb:
thefts, renters turned squatters, trashed homes and stolen identities. Yet
this ‘revolution in accommodation-seeking’ had 2.5 million users in 2012 and
has the traditional hotel industry so worried that they are trying to get it
banned in several cities.
Why do people enter into such risky bargains? And why, once
in them, don’t they tend to nick the lamps? Welcome to the problem of
cooperation, a field which straddles a huge number of academic departments,
from economics to anthropology, psychology to evolutionary biology, and aims to
explain, in a world in which so many interactions have a structure which allows
cheats to prosper at the expense of honest co-operators, why do agents cooperate? And how,
furthermore, might we get them to cooperate more?
In biology altruism is defined as behaviour
which is costly to the actor and beneficial to some recipient, where these
costs are understood in terms of fitness: reproductive advantage. Since the
inception of the field in the late 60s, the consensus has been that cooperation
in the strictest sense is impossible. No organism which behaves in a way which
makes it less fit can survive the survival of the fittest. In the human sciences costs and benefits are
understood as subjective payoffs. Here too, cooperation in games such as the
Prisoner’s Dilemma (where the payoffs are ordered such that, whatever your
partner chooses to do, your own score is always
highest if you cheat) was viewed to be inexplicable. It’s just not rational
to take a lower prize than is available and to leave yourself vulnerable to the
mercy of the other player. Cooperation – the occurrence of mutually beneficial
interactions in which neither party cheats to take advantage of obvious gains –
shouldn’t happen.
From defect to ubiquity
There are several reasons why, despite this, cooperation
wasn’t totally written off as an activity of the impaired or deranged. One of
them is the Major Transitions literature. Lynne Margulis, along with Maynard
Smith and Szathmary, can be credited for bringing the world’s attention to the
fact that most of the objects we take for granted as primitive elements in the
natural world – organisms, in other words – were in fact constructed out of smaller
building blocks. Human beings are the end-product of an iterative process which
has built aggregates out of aggregates out of aggregates of separate,
cooperating agents. We are mobile
agglomerates of what used to be separate cells. Our cells are unions of
separate prokaryote species. Prokaryote genomes are themselves alliances of
separate genes. The hierarchical structure of life proves that cooperation is
not just something we sometimes do, it is the cornerstone of biological
evolution and the process that brought us into existence.
So we have transitioned from seeing cooperation as a
marginal activity, limited to a few obscure phyla as in lichens, or present
only as a fleeting, maladaptive error, to accepting it as ubiquitous, eternal
and the central organising principle of life. It plays a critical explanatory
role in the behaviour of birds and bees, bacteria and nerve cells, plants and
genes and cancer cells, as well as the organisation of objects at multiple
hierarchical levels. Some now even define
the individual organism in terms of cooperation (Queller and Strassmann 2009).
What’s really going
on
The cooperation literature has been mostly focused on spelling
out various ways in which apparent cooperation
can be explained by better understanding what the real payoffs are, so that what initially looks altruistic is
revealed as serving the overall, long-term interests of the evolving agent. Evolution
is not about the survival of the less fit, full stop. But fitness effects can
be complex and convoluted, so that a strategy that appears costly might in fact
be beneficial on a longer view of things.
Ugly disputes have broken out about the most widely
applicable, or most elegant, or most sophisticated manner of performing this disclosure.
In Kin Selection Theory, the cost to the organism’s reproductive chances is
balanced by an indirect benefit to relatives who carry the same genes. In
Multilevel Selection theory, the cost to the individual is balanced by a
benefit to the group. In Decision Theory, the short-term cost is balanced by
the long-term prospect of reciprocation, or the benefits to self-esteem. Then
there are obscure side-effects, interaction patterns and coordination
procedures, all of which ensure that, whatever it may look like, the behaviour
in question is self-serving after all. Somewhat confusingly, Inclusive Fitness
Theory (Kin Selection’s modern update) expands
the notion of relatedness to encompass genetic assortment by any means. The
interactors need not be kin, in other words, they merely need to both be
members of the cooperative type. The very broadest view collects all the other
mechanisms together under the single banner of assortment. Kinship,
group-membership, signalling and clustering are all just different means of
raising the probability that when a cooperative behaviour is carried out, it is
another co-operator who receives the benefit. Once assortment is in place,
defectors struggle because they end up mostly interacting with other defectors.
Looking for the positives
In addition to explaining how the relationship between the
donor and the recipient can affect the stability of the interaction against
cheats, recent work seeks to shed light on what the point of cooperating is
anyway. What is it about social ventures, in other words, that makes them often
more profitable than going it alone? The two problems are entwined, because in
those interactions in which the partners are very different from one another,
it stands to reason that each might gain by bringing their different strengths
together. On the other hand, those partners that are most alike are in a better
position to trust one another, but its less obvious what they have to offer. As
David Queller has pointed out, clonal brothers are excellently placed to solve
the free rider problem, but there is a much smaller scope for synergistic
interactions between them, as compared to the different species of a mutualism. It seems that the less the partners stand to
lose from one another, the less they also stand to gain.
As well as settling how to keep cheaters from dodging their
share of the labour, or from manipulating their share of the profits, the
achievement of cooperation requires means of coordination. How is the labour to
be divided? How are the interaction partners to be chosen? How will each
partner know when it is time to play his part? How can the overall strategy be
made sensitive to the changing conditions in which the cooperative venture is
played out?
Mother nature’s solutions
Evolution has hit upon many different solutions to these
problems, each specific to the idiosyncrasies of the species and its
environment at that time, such as the nature and scope of the free-rider
threat, the abilities of the partners in question, the complexity of the group
task. For example, bacteria use a signalling system dubbed ‘quorum sensing’ to find
out when sufficient interaction partners are present to begin working on a
group task. Ants use pheromones, age-specific behaviours and special diets to
divide the labour between their members. A sort of invisible hand modulates colony
foraging behaviour, in some ant colonies, in response to changing availability
of food in the local environment. Each forager responds individually to the
rate at which it receives signals from incoming foragers, but the overall
result is a delicate sensitivity of whole-colony behaviour to current
conditions. Mole rat cooperatives are hierarchical, with control imposed from
above by the matriarchs of each group. Metazoan cell lineages are also
hierarchical, with gene transcription powers being increasingly removed as one
moves down a somatic cell lineage, and reproductive privileges clutched in the
control of a tiny, tightly-guarded minority.
We are discovering more and more ways in which biology has
bequeathed humans with cooperation triggers and short-circuits. Japanese
companies have known for years that making your workers participate in mass tai
chi sessions improves their group cohesion. We now know that participation in
synchronised physical movements triggers the release of endorphins in our
brains, making us feel more bonded to and more likely to cooperate with our
partners in the activity. I recall feeling desperately sorry for a flatmate of
mine whose weekend job on a supermarket checkout required him to do ‘the
Walmart Wiggle’ at monthly meetings. Of course, religions and armies caught on
years ago to the group-bonding power of synchronised movement.
Human emotions have been suggested as functioning to police
cooperation, with guilt increasing honesty within a group, romantic love
serving as a commitment device for reproductive cooperation, and disgust
constituting a deeply-felt over-ride to cooperative intentions. We know that
just gluing a poster showing a pair of eyes above an honesty jar makes users
more likely to pay. And it might be that we love soap operas so much because
they exercise our innate facility and enthusiasm for gossip, for the
dissemination and articulation of information concerning the cooperative
reputations of our peers.
As gross modifiers and constructors of our own niche , human
cooperation has long been under cultural, as well as biological, selection. We are
masters in the creation of arbitrary markers that will advertise our
affiliation to a group. We fabricate cultural myths and icons that create
justification for the demarcation of one group against others. We have
institutionalised commitment devices such as engagement rings, which make the
choice of defecting on a future marriage partner a little less attractive by
making it cost rather more.
How to cooperate
One of the pioneers of the field of cooperation studies was Robert
Axelrod. He studied cooperation in order
to find out how to get more of it. In a tale that is now legendary Axelrod set
about studying the matter by inviting scholars to play a huge game of
Prisoner’s Dilemma. In this game, the players meet each other in pairs and have
to choose to between two options, whose score depends on what the other partner
chooses. ‘Cooperate’ scores 3 if matched by the other player, but only 1 if
unmatched. ‘Defect’ scores 2 if matched by the other, but 4 if not. Axelrod put
all the players in a grand tournament in order to find a winning strategy. The
result was, at first, a clear and earth shattering victory for a strategy that
was decidedly cooperative. ‘Tit for Tat’ initiates each new relationship (i.e.
when playing the first round against each player) by choosing to cooperate.
After that, Tit for Tat earns it name by just doing whatever the other player
did last time. The world reported that the secret to successful interactions is
to be nice.
In the years that followed, that result has turned into a resounding
‘not so fast’, with subsequent research showing that there was rather an
element of luck in the winning strategy’s victory, that other, less nice
players would have won had they been entered. It was crucial, first of all,
that Axelrod’s tournament made players play over and over. One-shot prisoners’
dilemmas are insoluble, i.e. it only makes sense to defect. But put players in
an iterated situation, where they can learn from their experience and keep
track of the history of their interactions with other players, and suddenly
cooperation becomes not just reasonable, but a potentially winning
(high-scoring) strategy. Successive
experts have improved on Tit for Tat by designing strategies that are able to
break free where Tit for Tat gets locked into ongoing cycles of defection, as
well as strategies that are so ‘grim’ that even Tit for Tat gets mauled in
competition with them. Nonetheless, the tournament and Axelrod’s brilliant
analysis of it have generated a huge field which has yielded many priceless
insights to biologists, to philosophers, to governments and to everybody else.
Here is some advice, from Axelrod
and others, on how to make people cheat less:
- Make them feel more confident that cooperation will be reciprocated by;
- Reducing the effective group size, so that interactors are more likely to meet each other again.
- Facilitating accurate information about partner history, using social reputations, transparency
- Improving recognition capabilities or enabling the players to signal, share information.
- Make cheating more expensive, by imposing additional costs using;
- External threats and promises via laws, police forces, armies.
- External sources of commitment, such as contracts, deposits, trade.
- Internal sources of commitment, such as value systems, emotions, social norms.
The old old questions
Have we, as a species, become more cooperative, or less, in
the course of evolution? Some people take humans to be distinctive in the
extent and complexity of their cooperation. On this view, the need to monitor
interactions, to avoid cheats, and to coordinate group activities, was what
drove human intelligence and enabled our eventual domination of every niche on
the planet. Others instead think of cooperation as an ancestral state, arguing
that we were members of social collectives first, and that individualism is a
much more recent phenomenon.
All this goes back to issues concerning what is our human
nature, and has long been associated with political philosophical commitments.
If our nature is fundamentally competitive, red in tooth and claw, then some
take this as supporting social and economic conservatism, survival of the
fittest in the marketplace. If our evolved essence is cooperative,
collectivist, on the other hand, then modern capitalism is a distortion of our
natural order, and we can’t find happiness until we shake off these recent
consumerist perversions. The dichotomy has a long pedigree, but that it is
false is evidenced by alternatives: Peter Singer’s Darwinian Left, for one, Haim
Ofek’s Cooperative Marketeering, for another. We won’t settle normative
questions about right versus left by studying the evolution of cooperation. But
we can hope to better understand what conditions and mechanisms might help to
push a system towards either one equilibrium or the other. We might learn
something about which sort of coordination problems can be solved by
hierarchical order, and which by egalitarian organisation.
Axelrod recognised
the field’s applications as ranging from the grandest problems of public policy
and international relations (How can two nations negotiate mutual
disarmament?), to the simplest matters of our personal lives (How many times
will we invite acquaintances for dinner if they never invite us over in
return?) to the most prosaic biological conundrums (Why doesn’t the shark eat
the cleaner fish once it’s dental checkup is done?) Big business was quick to
identify the potential competitive advantages made possible by the study of
cooperation, but for Axelrod the goal was always to serve more altruistic ends,
to apply biological lessons to
make the world a more cooperative place (a goal still sought today in DS
Wilson’s ‘The Neighbourhood Project’, and also his exciting larger project, This view of life).
Back to Airbnb
In some ways, the success of Airbnb speaks against all the
received wisdom of the evolution of cooperation literature. The vendor and I don’t know each other, we
certainly are not kin. We are unlikely to interact with one another ever again,
especially if I’m on a city break. Yet here are two people – two strangers – who
are putting themselves in exceptionally vulnerable positions on each other’s
account, for fairly low pay offs.
Of course there are various rules and penalties designed to
prevent Airbnb users from taking advantage of each other, in addition to the
regular laws that countries enforce against murder, theft and so on. Basic id
and credit card checks go some way to protecting users. Nonetheless, the
website is carefully designed to emit vibes about trust, community, friendship,
rather than shouting about punishments or safety. Some users probably get a
psychological boost out of identifying with this adventurous,
anti-establishment, switched-on community (one of those convoluted, hidden
payoffs to apparent cooperation). And in an example of how complex things can
get when cooperation ‘games’ are nested inside one another, Airbnb itself
compensates users in order to protect its own reputation.
But there are two features that probably do most to underpin
the relatively cheater-free operation of Airbnb and other peer-to-peer services
such as RelayRides, TripAdvisor and eBay. One is the reliance on a rating or
review system. This allows users to build up an online reputation, from which
others can glean indirect information about how a person is going to behave, based
on her interactions with third parties. In an age where ‘community’ is more
likely to be found online than in any geographic locale, reviews systems
perform the role once carried out by village gossip.
Equally important and, perhaps, less obvious is the role of
the user profile. These are much more than mere avatars. It is not really about
making yourself less of a stranger, because there is no pretence that the
interaction will be iterated. As on dating websites, on which users seek to
choose a partner for the biggest cooperative challenge of all, writing the
profile is all about signalling to other players about what sort of partner you
will be. But it is no use just declaring
yourself honest (or fun, or good-looking, or whatever the other users are
looking for). Since the profiles are self-authored, such assertions won’t count
for much. What’s needed is some kind of hard-to-fake signal.
One strategy is to litter your profile with cues signalling
your membership of some group. Throw in personal details to prove you have the expected
nationality, that you’re not computer generated, or a fronting a commercial business. But more importantly,
a few details so that you can be identified as a member of a social tribe: a
little left-leaning here, a nod to being literary there. Maybe you enjoy real
ale. Maybe there is a bicycle visible in
your profile picture, or its a shot of you performing at your local open-mic
night. Other members of this type – middle-class, educated, urban – can pick
these cues up and use them as a basis upon which to assort with you. Once a
user has identified you as a member of their social tribe they are much more
likely to trust you, to want to cooperate with you. You are someone they might
chat to in a cafĂ©, someone their sister might date. “We’re from the same
cultural clan.....” the profile whispers, “Trust me!”
The user profile is an assortment device, a source of honest
signals to help us find people who share our values, whom we can rely on.
Liberals, goths, mods and rockers, wine snobs or born-again
Christians........we humans like to assort with partners who we deem to be
co-members of some culturally constructed group. Axelrod explained that arbitrary observable
markers, just as much as anything with an objective basis such as sex, support
stable stereotypes, in which players act under the assumption that their
partner will behave similarly to others of that label. What’s more, these stereotypes can become
self-confirming, because once everybody expects a certain behaviour of you, its
optimal to exhibit just that behaviour.
If people expect you to cheat, they’ll try to cheat you first, so you’d better
not become the sucker.
The signals we send are generally reliable because, thanks
to the notoriously rapid pace at which cultural tribes evolve (hipster,
anyone?), they are difficult to fake. You have to be a genuine signed-up member
of a clique to have any chance of getting it right.
Cooperation without limit?
We have learnt much about the powerful cooperative forces
that have shaped and built living organisms. In a 2007 paper the evolutionary
biologist Stephen C Stearns asked, of humanity, ‘Are we stalled part way
through a major evolutionary transition from individual to group?’ His
supposition was that cultural group selection has brought about sufficient
genetic change that people are in many ways optimised for group traits. In
other words, many of our innate drives serve group-level purposes, rather than promoting
our selfish interests as human beings.
Stearns doesn’t think the transition is likely to be
completed, for technical reasons to do with heritability. So he doesn’t think
that men and women will likely ever end up as mere parts whose interests are subjugated
to that of a greater whole. But it is hard to resist imagining this dystopian
scifi future. It is a world in which a totalitarian Marxist dream is realised,
where individual humans cease to exist as separable agents, only a handful of
elites reproduce and all the others sacrifice their every effort
unquestioningly to the support of those elites. Of course it sounds terrifying,
immoral, but biology knows no morality and did not hesitate before imposing the
very same fate on our cells. Will a future, more advanced morality mourn the
cruelties imposed on these cells, our own ancestors? Might we one day celebrate
the heroic individualistic rebellion of cancer cells, just as the west
celebrated those who fought the dehumanising shackles of soviet communitarianism?
Of course not, but the point is that the tension between our
collectivist instincts and our individualist instincts is ancient and
pervasive. In-group/out-group distinctions colour much of our interaction with
one another, with sometimes very profitable but sometimes most horrific
consequences. Many of the most important domains of human intellect are touched
by issues about how to balance the interests of wholes against parts. We can do
no better to further these issues than to ask mother nature why she sometimes
tips the balance one way or the other, how she does it, and what the
consequences are.
Further reading
Samir Okasha, ‘Evolution and the Levels of Selection’, OUP
2006.
Kim Sterelny, Richard Joyce, Brett
Calcott and Ben Fraser (eds) ‘Cooperation and its Evolution’, MIT Press 2014.
No comments:
Post a Comment